If Woolfâs criticism was Paterian in its vision of the relationship between reader and text, then that of Murry, and his fellow editor A. R. Orage, was firmly Arnoldian. Both saw literature as essential to the upholding of a certain set of values, generally characterised in terms of an appeal to âtruthsâ that could rescue the age from the social and spiritual prob- lems it faced. Indeed, Orage chose an explicitly Arnoldian formulation in describing culture as âthe disinterested pursuit of human perfectionâ, with literature â a âvaluable instrument of truthâ â being uniquely able to make this âtruthâ part of humanityâs common experience.79 For Murry, literature could fulfil spiritual and emotional needs that were no longer assuaged by âsocial or religious securityâ: in The Problem of Style, he described a respect for Thomas Hardy as evidence of âa hunger, if not for religion, for the peace of an attitude of mind which might with some truth be called religiousâ.80 This Arnoldian vision of the redemptive power of criticism had obvious consequences for the criticâs role. While Murry believed that every reader had the potential to be a critic, he also insisted that the critic possessed a set of skills that elevated him above the ordinary reader. On one level, these skills consisted of the capacity to act as a mediator in performing an explication of the text, helping the reader to understand âthe unique and essential quality of his authorâ by removing âsome of the obstacles that stand in the way of an immediate contact between this quality and the readerâs mindâ and offering a privileged insight into the âtruthâ contained within the text.81 In addition, the critic also acted as an evaluator. The lectures that make up The Problem of Style are peppered with terms that attest to this role: authors are seen in terms of their âvitalityâ, âperfectionâ or âtrivialityâ; novels are divided simply into âgoodâ and âbadâ; a passage of Arnold Bennett displays âdownright wickednessâ.82 In a similar way, Orage saw âtruthâ as linked inextricably to the concept of âcommon senseâ, being something that âeverybody knows but needs to be reminded that he knowsâ.83 These âremindersâ needed to be issued by critics able to recognise and communicate this truth, people who were both part of the common domain of humanity yet also set apart from it by their possession of a superior kind of knowledge. In turn, this knowledge had to be communicated in a manner that was âcapable of being understood by the jury of mankindâ: the images of judge and jury that pervade his critical writing reflect the seriousness with which he saw literary criticism, a process vital to the health of society.84 Both Murry and Orage, then, elevated the critic above Woolfâs âcommon readerâ and gave him the role of sage, a figure endowed not just with knowledge, but also with wisdom. Significantly, this was a role they also claimed for themselves. They did this partly through their criticism, but also â perhaps more crucially â through their work as editors, a task which gave their critical work a more specific context and direction. It is important to note that the journals Murry and Orage edited were not exclusively literary, but contained articles on a range of topics felt to be relevant to the issue of culture and society. Orage, whose weekly magazine The New Age has been described by Wallace Martin as âan unparalleled arena of cultural and political debateâ,85 was vehemently anti-specialist, criticising both the narrow-mindedness of âaesthetic fastidiousnessâ and the âdullâ outlook that resulted from an overemphasis of âhistory, foreign affairs, [and] economicsâ.86 During his editorship of The New Age, which lasted from 1907 to 1922, Orage aimed to bring together politics, literature and the arts in an attempt to address the social, cultural and economic problems of the time through a coherent philosophy of life rather than in empirical terms. In doing this, he also hoped to counter the fragmentation that had been brought about by the specialisation of academic disciplines and the diversification of the arts. Consequently, The New Age was intended to appeal to a broad social spectrum: both the new thinkers and readers created by the growth of secondary and higher education, and the old audiences of the Victorian periodicals, dissatisfied by the way that these journals had modified their content to keep up with the demands of the mass market.87 This non- specialist aim was shared by Murry in his editorship of the Adelphi, a journal that consciously played on its audienceâs sense of urgency at the supposed breakdown of an educated reading public and the displace- ment of criticism into academic analysis. Even when Murry resigned as editor, it is significant that his successors, Max Plowman and Richard Rees, were keen to advertise their desire to carry on his work rather than creating a break with his aims, presenting the Adelphi as part of a humanist attempt to seek âa sense of values commensurate with the glory of life and the majesty of deathâ in a battle against âcynical indifference, super- ficial wit, [and] otiose amiabilityâ.88 Such sentiments are clearly part of what Stefan Collini has described as an early twentieth-century nostalgia for the ideal of the coherent Victorian reading public, an important strand of which was an insist- ence on the âdebasedâ nature of the contemporary media and the lack of seriousness engendered by the popular press and its focus on leisure and amusement.89 It is therefore all the more significant that Murryâs criticism and presence continued to dominate the Adelphi even after his editorship ceased. In the year after Murryâs resignation, the Adelphi contained essays by Murry on the influence of Lord Northcliffe and on modern religion, as well as a series of reminiscences of D. H. Lawrence; he was to contribute more articles and reviews in the future. In addition, Plowman and Rees did their best to consolidate Murry in the role of sage. Their first editorial described his resignation as a release from âhumbler dutiesâ, allowing him to devote his time to the more important tasks of literary and cultural criticism.90 In a review of Murryâs Discoveries and Studies in Keats, Plowman described him in terms that fore- ground his humane qualities rather than any academic achievements, seeing his âsimple sincerityâ, âreverence for common thingsâ and âquiet depth of feelingâ as revealing a truth whose value was, implicitly, much more substantial.91 According to Plowman, Discoveries contained  the sober evaluations of a widely informed, even learned mind. It is beautifully written, in that it is âthe complete and coherent utterance of a man who feels and sees and thinks clearly and is convinced that his feeling and vision and thought is worth utteranceâ. Each essay fulfils the authorâs intent in being âthe adventures of a manâs soul among booksâ, and surpasses that intention by adventuring deeply into the souls of those who wrote the books. The discoveries are not the usual discoveries of the modern essayist â of mareâs nests facetiously disguised â but are genuine and personal discoveries, of purpose, felicity and meaning, which reveal different aspects of truth as it appears in great work.92
In Studies in Keats, meanwhile, Keats was ânot disintegrated by analysis, nor intellectualised into a poetic cypher, but better known both in his likeness and in his unlikeness to ourselvesâ.93 Such statements posit an opposition between academic analysis and the more spiritual (and, implicitly, more far-reaching) criticism of those who were prepared to meet literature on its own terms, making themselves humble before the âgreatnessâ of the text. In contrast to the analytical techniques associ- ated with academic criticism, Murryâs work was âan adventure of the soul, a delivery of himself up to the test all great literature makes of those capable of its appreciationâ.94 It is clear from such statements that the authority Plowman claimed for Murry was grounded in non-specialist skills and values. Murry himself saw the source of critical authority as an important topic and was frequently scathing about the value of scholarship, emphasising instead a form of knowledge that could not be generated by academic analysis. In a review of The Wheel of Fire, Murry criticised the Shakespeare scholar G. Wilson Knight for wanting âto prove too much, to delve too deepâ, and commented that âhe does not deepen, but does violence to our imme- diate impression of Shakespeareâs playsâ. Furthermore, he claimed that Shakespeare âis to Mr. Wilson Knight different from what he is to me. I can scarcely recognise some of the plays after they have passed through the process of âinterpretationâ to which he submits them.â95 What Murry considered important was not the professional validity of Wilson Knightâs work, but the protection of Shakespeareâs integrity: the critic must be careful to restrict his or her work to an investigation of the humane elements of literature, balancing the desire for knowledge against the need to produce interpretations that will sustain and give hope. Orage was also keen to reject the notion that literary analysis had to be scholarly. In an article in the New English Weekly in 1932, he dismissed an argument put forward by Sir Josiah Stamp (then Governor of the Bank of England) that called for the revival of a form of intelli- gence defined by âthe application of scientific methods to a continually widening area of human experienceâ, stating that scientific reason was only one form of reason.96 This drew on his earlier desire to use The New Age to advance the idea that reason itself was only one faculty among many, none of which should be ignored. In 1917, he had urged readers of The New Age to âsuspend final judgment until complete harmony has been established, until, in short, the brain and the heart are of one mindâ.97 In emphasising the role of the heart as well as that of the brain, Orage was able to ground criticism in qualities that were easily rendered mysterious, stating that the âmessageâ of the greatest books could only be grasped intuitively. In an editorial written in 1919, he claimed that âthe âsubconsciousâ of every great book […] is vastly greater than its conscious element [. . .] We may be unable indeed to put into words any of the ideas we have gathered.â98 If one conse- quence of academic professionalisation was to make disciplines more conscious of the methods and procedures they adopted, then Orage was taking criticism in quite the opposite direction: his insistence that it rested on processes that could not be articulated meant that it was not available for further analysis, placing it beyond the scope of academic enquiry. The mysteriousness with which Orage surrounded the act of criticism can be interpreted as a response to a dilemma that Guy and Small have detected in the work of both Orage and Murry, namely that while both critics attempt to authorise their judgements through an appeal to com- mon values and experience, they also had to claim for themselves the privileged insight that would justify and protect their role.99 Both Orage and Murry stated that everyone had the potential to be a critic, with the âcommon senseâ upon which criticism rested being latent in the minds of everyone. In 1918, Orage wrote that right judgement was never purely personal: âIts essential character […] is simply that it is right; right how- ever arrived at, and right whoever arrives at it.â100 But if everyone could act as their own critic, then the status of the sage would be undermined. As we have seen, one potential solution was to invest this role with a set of skills that would separate it from the lesser capacities of the leisured reader. However, attempts to carry this out often led to further contradic- tions. While Orage, for instance, claimed that âthe best judgements commend themselves to the common sense of even the average juryâ, that âany average body of readers could be brought to appreciate the justness of every sound literary judgmentâ, he also dismissed the idea that âTom,
Dick and Harryâ should be invited to âoffer their opinions as of equal value with the opinions of the cultivatedâ.101 There is a certain slippage between these two positions: the former elevates the âmassâ of ordinary readers, while the latter (influenced perhaps by Orageâs distaste for the very real phenomenon of the mass market) dismisses the ordinary readerâs capacity to make critical judgements.102 The situation that results from this is highly problematic: while the average reader is unable to produce the kind of judgements made by the cultivated critic, these judgements needed to be secured by the assent of the average reader in order to have any kind of validity. This dilemma over the status of the critic often leads to a particular self-consciousness about language and method. In Murryâs The Problem of Style, this self-consciousness takes the form of an attempt to find a precise language in which to define the criticâs role. Murryâs initial statements about criticism appear as a celebration of its vagueness, which is presented as a positive alternative to the âideal of definitionâ by which the critic is often preoccupied:
The critic becomes dissatisfied with the vagueness of his activity, or his art; and he will indulge the fantastic dream that it might be reduced to the firm precision of a science. He may even, during this period of dissatisfaction, forget that half the fascination of his task lies in the fact that the terms he uses are fluid and uncertain, and that his success depends upon the compulsive vigour with which he impresses upon them a meaning which shall be exactly fitted to his own invention and unmistakable by his audience.103
On one level, this definition of criticism acts as a justification of Murryâs right to define âstyleâ on his own terms: as a non-academic critic speaking in an academic setting, he speaks out on behalf of the authority of the individual. This can, in turn, be read as a vindication of Murryâs right to be taken seriously. If critical authority rests on individ- ual skill rather than the fact of institutional employment, then the amateur critic still has a role to play. Yet elsewhere in these lectures, Murryâs celebration of the âfluidity and uncertaintyâ of critical expres- sion is replaced by an attempt to isolate a more precise kind of language in which critical judgements can be uttered. The need for this precision is hinted at early on, in Murryâs definition of the criticâs task as âto recreate in his reader the peculiar emotion aroused in him by a work of literatureâ104 â to convey, as precisely as possible, the effect of reading a particular text. And as Murry goes on, his search for this method of
âprecise communicationâ involves the use of algebraic formulae, as he strives to articulate the difficulty of achieving such a form:
To [communicate an emotion], I have to find some symbol which will evoke in [the reader] an emotional reaction as nearly as possible identical with the emotion I am feeling. Do not mistake me when I say symbol; I use the word because I cannot think of a better at the moment; I mean to include in it any device of expression which is not merely descriptive […] But on both sides there is unfortunately an unknown quantity: my temperament is an x, my readerâs is a y. The product that results from the combination of those given circum- stances with x may be, probably will be, very different from their combination with y.105
Murryâs initial rejection of âthe firm precision of a scienceâ is there- fore replaced by a sense that the conventional vocabulary of literary criticism lacks the precision that is required for such complex definitions: the essential problem facing Murry is the problem of style itself. In turn, it seems that Murryâs attempt to explain this problem becomes a further way of securing his authority. In working at this metacritical level, Murry suggests that he has a wider grasp of what the criticâs role involves that allows him to move from the particular to the general, making oracular statements about the task of both the critic and the creative artist. And in addition, the task of criticism is given a status that takes it beyond mere impressionism: when we analyse style, âwe are making not so much a literary as a scientific or even an ethical judgementâ.106 Murryâs rhetoric therefore helps to consolidate his authority by drawing attention to his own perception of the task in which he is engaged: his audience is kept constantly aware of both the importance of this task and the difficulty of performing it correctly.
In spite of the diversity of their practices and beliefs, what links the criticism of Woolf, Murry and Orage is a shared emphasis on knowledge and processes that remained intangible. Woolfâs impressionism and the focus on judgement shared by Orage and Murry both located the import- ance of the text in its effect on a particular kind of reader, positioned between the scholars and the masses: either as part of a pleasurable yet rigorous experience or within a project of cultural renewal. Their own critical pronouncements rested, moreover, on forms of authority that were personal rather than professional, underpinned by rhetoric and by an appeal to a kind of knowledge that was shrouded in mystique. As a result, none of these writers produced a model of literary criticism that was teachable. Instead, they occupied a varied range of positions in which literary criticism was neither an academic discipline nor a form of leisure: it was too important to leave either to the whims of the masses or to the misdirected pedantry of scholarship.