Such a focus on language gives many of Eliotâs writings a characteristic structure that is at once an echo of Walter Bagehotâs notion of the âreview-like essayâ,33 and a potential blueprint for an academic essay that could demonstrate the capacity for judgement as well as know- ledge that he praised in the work of W. P. Ker. Eliotâs early periodical essays typically begin by quoting an accepted view of the writer in question, and then examine its validity through a close analysis of style and theme, a technique described by F. W. Bateson as embodying a scepticism whose âcontinuous invitation […] to dig below the verbal or conventional surfaceâ gave Eliotâs early work much of its rigour.34 Yet this rigour is not consistent in its application. At many points in Eliotâs work, quotations are used not as the starting-point for an analysis of language and form, but as a means of justifying evaluative comments that are presented as objective, all-encompassing truths. When comparing Massinger to Shakespeare, Eliot opines that âwhile the lines of Massinger have their own beautyâ, they remain inferior:Â âa âbright exhalationâ appeals to the eye and makes us catch our breath in the evening; âmeteorâ is a dim simile; the word is wornâ.35 The normative use of plural pronouns gives Eliotâs judgements an authoritative sweep that elevates them above the purely personal, echoing the rhetoric of the âmen of lettersâ in its attempt to create a sense of objectivity. Later in the same essay, Eliotâs judgements become more expansive, encompassing not just stylistic technique but the whole of an authorâs vision:
Marloweâs and Jonsonâs comedies were a view of life; they were, as great literature is, the transformation of a personality into a personal work of art, their lifetimeâs work, long or short. Massinger is not simply a smaller personality: his personality hardly exists. He did not, out of his own personality, build a work of art, as Shakespeare and Marlowe and Jonson built.36
Here, beliefs about the relationship of text and author, and about the relative success of the authors Eliot mentions, are asserted with the impersonality of fact. For J. Hillis Miller, such impersonality is purely illusory, a trick of rhetoric that substitutes the appearance of a univer- sal mind for the private mind of Eliot himself: âin neither case can there be an encounter with anything other than mentalâ.37 Yet this impersonal rhetoric is an important factor in maintaining Eliotâs critical authority. The broad historical range of his work, together with his presentation of tradition as an order and a system of which he had a complete understanding, gives his criticism a sense of objec- tivity that seems to expect no dissent. The importance Eliot placed on judgement â on âthe criticâs ability to tell a good poem from a bad oneâ â adds to this air of confidence: while it is unspoken, Eliotâs belief in his own ability to carry out this task is apparent throughout his work.38 This belief in the centrality of judgement often leads Eliot to adopt a critical position that seems entirely at odds with the authority of the academic. While many of his essays do draw attention to judgements that are rooted in factual knowledge, others seem to revel in exposing gaps in this knowledge, even flaunting them as evidence that the critic has a right to voice judgements even when they are unsup- ported. His discussion of versification in âThe Music of Poetryâ is accompanied by the admission that âI have never been able to retain the names of feet and metres, or to pay the proper respect to the accepted rules of scansion.â39 In The Use of Poetry and the Use of Criticism, Eliotâs attitude towards Coleridgeâs theory of imagination seems decidedly casual:
I have read some of Hegel and Fichte, as well as Hartley (who turns up at any moment with Coleridge), and forgotten it; of Schelling I am entirely ignorant at first hand, and he is one of those numerous authors whom, the longer you leave them unread, the less desire you have to read. Hence it may be that I wholly fail to appreciate this passage. My mind is too heavy and concrete for any flight of abso- lute reasoning. If, as I have already suggested, the difference between imagination and fancy amounts in practice to no more than the difference between good and bad poetry, have we done more than take a turn round Robin Hoodâs barn?40
Such claims may well have been disingenuous, an attempt to lessen the gap between Eliot and his audience rather than a genuine admission of ignorance. Yet it is important to note that Eliotâs brusque rejection of Coleridgeâs philosophy (and the knowledge that supported it) places him firmly in the camp of the generalist: one who may be rescued by his own authority as a poet, but who nevertheless is emphatically not an academic specialist.41 This personal stance is also apparent in Eliotâs discussion of Shelley, in which he makes it perfectly plain that he is approaching Shelley as an interested amateur rather than a scholar: âI find his ideas repellent […] the man was humourless, pedantic, self- centred, and almost a blackguard.â42 Eliotâs overt rejection of scholarly knowledge highlights his ambivalence about the value of a form of criticism that was dominated by the needs of specialisation. Chris Baldick points out that while the âuniversity English Studies movementâ was able (as Louis Menand has claimed) to âexpand upon Eliotâs early promise [by] appropriating his critical innovations […] and using them for its own purposesâ, this process of appropriation was âoften against [Eliotâs] willâ, taking criticism in a direction of which Eliot would not have approved.43 One of the most pertinent examples of this is in the formalist analysis that E. M. W. Tillyard defined as a major influence on the work of I. A. Richards. For Tillyard, âthe change of taste typified and promoted by Eliot, the reaction from Romantic emotionalism to more cerebral types of poetry, fostered the urge towards practical criticism because it directed attention to a kind of literature for which minute exegesis was especially aptâ.44 Yet Eliot himself felt that such exegesis did not necessarily assist the ordinary reader, as it carried with it an assumption that poetry was invariably difficult â thus throwing the reader into âa state of consternation very unfavourable to poetic receptivityâ.45 He also believed that the critic must bear in mind the relevance of the knowledge he or she sought to produce. In âThe Function of Criticismâ, he insists that while the criticâs chief tools are comparison and analysis, âit is obvious indeed that they are tools, to be handled with care, and not employed in an inquiry into the number of times giraffes are mentioned in the English novelâ.46 A similar view, albeit more soberly phrased, is expressed in âThe Perfect Criticâ, in which technical criticism is seen as âlimitedâ in its aims.47 Meanwhile, in âThe Frontiers of Criticismâ (1956), Eliot acknowledged that while âmost of the really interesting criticism to-day is the work of men of letters who have found their way into the universities, and of scholars whose critical activity has first been exercised in the classroomâ, the resulting level of specialisation threatened to deaden true critical insight, producing a kind of knowledge typified by the âexplanation by originsâ of John Livingston Lowesâs The Road to Xanadu, or by âthe lemon-squeezer schoolâ of Practical Criticism. Neither approach would succeed in fostering a genuine understanding of literature. The former â like the âbogus scholarshipâ of Eliotâs own notes to The Waste Land â offered little more than a puzzle invented âfor the pleasure of discovering the solutionâ, accumulating knowledge yet failing to use this for any real purpose.48 The latter closed off the possibility of individual thought by claiming to offer a single, univocal interpretation of the text: âThere are many things, perhaps, to know about this poem, or that, many facts about which scholars can instruct me which will help me to avoid definite misunderstanding; but a valid interpretation, I believe, must be at the same time an interpretation of my own feelings when I read it. â49 Perhaps more important, however, was the sense that such approaches also pointed to a loss of critical direction. Recognising the changing nature of the âseriousâ reading public, and the narrowing of the potential audience for criticism, Eliot wondered âwhether the weak- ness of modern criticism is not an uncertainty as to what criticism is for […] what benefit it is to bring, and to whomâ.50 If criticism was to carry out its task of reasserting and reinterpreting the literary tradition to a world in crisis, it had to avoid both the subjectivity of aestheticism and a retreat into academic isolation. Eliotâs criticism therefore offered a number of methods and philosophies to academic departments of English. Its early insistence on rigour and impersonality, and on the importance of critical method, gave implicit support to the subjectâs claims to disciplinarity: to read Eliotâs criticism is to be aware of an activity that was at once wide-ranging, difficult and important. Yet this importance brought responsibility, and this responsibility â to a society constantly depicted as in danger of losing its sense of its culture â could not be fulfilled if English was allowed to remain a purely specialist pursuit. For criticism to carry out its âsocial missionâ, it would need to have a wider audience and a wider frame of reference.