Eliotâs rejection of the âlemon-squeezer school of criticismâ also adds an ironic twist to Tillyardâs claim that Eliot was himself a central figure in the development of such a school, promoting critical rigour and the need for the âminute exegesisâ of difficult texts. By 1956, Eliot had become con- vinced that criticism should be directed towards enjoyment as well as understanding, and was afraid that analysis would put the ordinary readerâs experience of the text in jeopardy, hinting at a level of difficulty that was not necessarily present. Yet this was also a view that Richards himself came to espouse. In a conversation in December 1968, Richards stated that âmaking [English] into an academic subject has not increased the amount of enjoyment taken in the poems […] I think weâre burying the valuables under a whole load of derivativesâ.51 Eliotâs reduction of practical criticism to mere âlemon-squeezingâ was also based on a mis- reading of Richardsâs aims. While Richards did indeed see a structured, analytical approach to literature as important to an understanding of the text, this was formulated not in specialised, academic terms, but as the only appropriate response to the crisis faced by literature in the modern world â a crisis that had also been perceived by Eliot himself. The precise extent of Eliot and Richardsâs influence upon each other is difficult to isolate. John Paul Russo, Richardsâs biographer, suggests that their effect on each othersâ criticism and philosophy âcannot be asserted with assuranceâ, but nevertheless concedes that âit cannot be said that they arrived at certain positions without studying each othersâ workâ.52 Even so, critics have differed in their evaluation of this study. While Tillyard saw Eliotâs direction of attention to âmore cerebral types of poetryâ as crucial to the emergence of practical criticism, John Constable has argued that Richards (unlike many of his Cambridge contemporaries) did not use The Sacred Wood as a âprimary textâ in the development of his own critical method, with his textual annotations being âshort and dismissiveâ.53 Eliot and Richards also disagreed on several points. In his Norton Lectures, Eliot was openly critical of Richardsâs recommendation of a set of âspiritual exercisesâ designed to heighten the readerâs response to poetry.54 Earlier, in an article in The Dial, he had heaped scorn on Richardsâs belief that poetry âis capable of saving usâ: âPoetry âis capable of saving us,â he says; it is like saying that the wall-paper will save us when the walls have crumbled.â55 Richards was more muted in his censure of Eliotâs work, but still disagreed with aspects of his style and practice, commenting in a marginal annotation in his copy of Eliotâs Homage to John Dryden (1924) that âT. S. E. always writes as thoâ he were God. Here the fact that HE is going to say some- thing about Dryden is going to alter everything for ever.â56 Yet importantly, both men saw criticism as a rigorous process that involved careful comparison and analysis, with Richardsâs formulation of criticism as âthe endeavour to discriminate between experiences and to evaluate themâ both echoing Paterâs emphasis on discrimination and foreshadowing Eliotâs description of the classification and comparison of experiences in The Use of Poetry and the Use of Criticism.57 In addition, both men also conceded that literary criticism had to involve a wider analysis of society and its values. While Eliot sought to protect poetry from the belief that it could be âreligion or an equivalent of religionâ, he later stated that âit is impossible to fence off literary criticism from criticism on other grounds […] moral, religious and social judgments cannot be wholly excludedâ.58 And while Richardsâs concept of âpseudo- statementsâ led him to challenge the belief that poetry could offer the same kind of verifiable truths as science, he also emphasised that literature and morality were intimately related: âThe common avoidance of all discussion of the wider social and moral aspects of the arts by people of steady judgment and strong heads is a misfortune.â59 Indeed, this philosophy of the arts came to underpin Richardsâs sense of the importance of interpretation: for Richards, the interpretative act was central to a complete grasp of the value of all art. Nevertheless, Richards also shared with Eliot certain doubts about the value of academic literary study. He was convinced that interpretation should be the focus of academic attention, and was scathing about the cursory treatment it had previously been given, commenting in Practical Criticism that one would expect that our libraries would be full of works on the theory of interpretation, the diagnosis of linguistic situations, systematic ambiguity and the functions of complex symbols […] Yet, in point of fact, there is no respectable treatise on the theory of linguistic interpretation in existence, and no person whose profes- sional occupation it is to inquire into these questions and direct study into the matter.However, he also made it clear that such an inquiry should not be limited to the study of literature, pointing out that âdirect training in readingâ would also be beneficial to âsuch studies as economics, psy- chology, political theory, law or philosophyâ.61 In addition, the study of interpretation was not to be confined to academia, but extended to society at large through programmes of education at all levels. Indeed, Richards stated, at a meeting of graduate students at Harvard in 1969, that graduate programmes in English âshould be dropped altogetherâ, as scholarship and criticism were a special calling that could only be enjoyed by a select few: global literacy and high-school teaching (of the kind promoted by Richardsâs work on âBasic Englishâ) were far more important than the specialist pursuit of writing âbooks-about-books-about-books and reviews of themâ.62 The fact that the development of English as an academic discipline was not one of Richardsâs specific aims means that his relationship with the subject is problematic. His belief in the importance of interpretation, and his formulation of a methodology for the systematic investigation of meaning, may well have helped to give literary criticism a rigour that it did not otherwise possess, focusing on the text itself rather than the investigation of sources, analogues and bibliographical matters that was emphasised by academic textual study. Yet Richardsâs emphasis on interpretation was not strictly concerned with literature alone. Instead, it reached beyond literature into the wider sphere of experience, a sphere also stressed by the rhetoric of Hugh James Rose and John Churton Collins. Their desire to give criticism a wider role paradoxically hindered its achievement of the academic status that rested on its capacity for special- isation. In Richardsâs formulation, the need for criticism and interpreta- tion to be of wider use creates a constant tension between specialism and utility â and in Richardsâs own career, the latter eventually won. Richardsâs sense of the importance of interpretation, expressed in both Principles of Literary Criticism (1924) and Practical Criticism (1929), was driven by the need to define a set of standards by which the value of the arts could be expressed. In Principles of Literary Criticism, this value is seen as being threatened by two specific forces: the ânarrowing and restrictionâ to which art had been subjected by aesthetic philosophy, and the more general debasing and commercialisation of culture that was taking place within contemporary society, resulting in the decreasing merit of ââbest-sellersâ […] magazine verses, mantelpiece pottery, Academy pictures, Music Hall songs, County Council buildings, [and] War Memorialsâ.63 These forces had brought about the urgent need for âa general theory of valueâ that was able to account for âthe place and function of the arts
in the whole system of valuesâ, defending the arts from the values of both capitalism and an empty aestheticism.64 Richardsâs sense of the importance of such a project is apparent in the metaphors of attack and defence in the following passage:
We need weapons with which to repel and over-throw misconcep- tions. With the increase of population the problem presented by the gulf between what is preferred by the majority and what is accepted as excellent by the most qualified opinion has become infinitely more serious and likely to become threatening in the near future. For many reasons standards are much more in need of defence than they used to be […] To bridge the gulf, to bring the level of popular appre- ciation nearer to the consensus of best qualified opinion, and to defend this opinion against damaging attacks […] a much clearer account than has yet been produced, of why this opinion is right, is essential. […] The expert in matters of taste is in an awkward position when he differs from the majority. He is forced to say, in effect, âI am better than you. My taste is more refined, my nature more cultured, you will do well to become more like me than you areâ. It is not his fault that he has to be so arrogant. He may, and usually does, disguise the fact as far as possible, but his claim to be heard as an expert depends upon the truth of these assumptions. He ought then to be ready with reasons of a clear and convincing kind as to why his preferences are worth attention.65
Such language attests vividly to Richardsâs sense of threat, and also to a certain insecurity about the role of the âexpert in matters of tasteâ, whose uneasiness is presented as ample justification for the theory of value Richards proposes. Significantly, while this âexpertâ is not defined in academic terms, it is important to note that what Richards is calling for is a means of securing expert authority and defining it as concerned with something that is more objective than the simple assertion of personal taste. Richards was some way from formulating the detailed methods of analysis proposed in Practical Criticism, but he was, never- theless, carrying out what Francis Mulhern has described as a âdeliberate repudiation of the amateurism of belles lettresâ, emphasising the need to shift criticism onto more objective grounds.66 Richardsâs work on interpretation, seen by Ian MacKillop as providing ânew, basic concepts for criticismâ,67 aimed to secure this objectivity by drawing on his belief that language could be analysed according to clear, scientific principles. Such a belief would help to locate judgement
(and therefore evaluation) in the process of analysis, a meticulous inves- tigation of the textâs formal properties and their shaping of meaning. Richardsâs 1926 work Science and Poetry (later reissued as Poetries and Sciences) argued for a dramatic change in the way in which the language of poetry was discussed, complaining that âwe think and talk in terms which merge and confound orders which must be distinguishedâ.68 To combat such confusion, Richards proposed a method of inquiry that would unite psychology and literature in a task for which neither the professional psychologist nor the man of letters had so far been equipped: a systematic analysis of the experience of reading. Richardsâs attempts to outline this process of inquiry show a clear desire to estab- lish a set of scientific principles appropriate to the description of literary meaning. His set of specialised quotation marks, developed in How to Read a Page (1943) and included in his 1970 Commentary to Poetries and Sciences, represents an attempt to distinguish between different types of meaning, such as ambiguities, specialised meanings, and words requiring particular attention.69 In addition, his description of the reading process demonstrates his desire to draw on the language and conceptual models of psychology, with reading being defined in terms of a process of âagitationâ set up by âthe impression of the printed words on the retinaâ, and continuing with the separation of this âagitationâ into intellectual and emotional streams. For the mind, âa system of very delicately poised balancesâ, each experience requires a rearranging of thought and emotion in order to achieve a state of harmony, with poetry being regarded as particularly effective in creating a state of mental equili- brium.70 The poetâs capacity for ordering speech, and the readerâs ability to interpret this order, thus become central to Richardsâs concept of poetic value: poetry is, in effect, representative of a wider capacity for the ordering of experience that is essential to the attainment of mental stability. It is important to note here that Richardsâs theory of value differs from a concept of value that is based on the morality inherent in the literary text, of that kind envisioned in the Marxist model of English studies as an aggressive means of promoting a certain kind of culture. His description of critical method rarely turns to individual authors; and indeed in Practical Criticism he shifts the focus of questions of value from the text itself to the mind of the reader:
Instead of an illusory problem about values supposed to inhere in poems […] we have a real problem about the relative values of different states of mind, about varying forms, and degrees, of order in the
personality. […] It is less important to like âgoodâ poetry and dislike âbad,â than to be able to use them both as a means of ordering our minds.71
Crucially, it is this sense of order that is of lasting benefit to the reader, and which will be carried out into the world at large. In the closing pages of Practical Criticism Richards expresses this philosophy through a quotation from Matthew Arnold: a âcommerce with the ancientsâ appears to Arnold to produce, âin those who constantly practise it, a steadying and composing effect upon their judgment, not of literary works only, but of men and events in generalâ.72 Richardsâs emphasis on the ordering of experience also recalls Eliotâs focus on the reordering of tradition, with both processes foregrounding the need for impersonality and discrimination. For both Eliot and Richards, the importance of poetry lay in its rigorous organisation of both language and experience, rather than in the crude communication of a definite set of morals and values. Poetries and Sciences, then, represents Richardsâs attempt to formulate a model of reading that was based on scientific principles, drawing on his background in the moral sciences â a background that gave Richards a unique position within Cambridgeâs English Faculty â to âevaluat[e] the precise activity of the human mindâ.73 However, in Practical Criticism, Richards acknowledged that communication and interpretation are not always precise, straightforward processes. His study of the âprotocolsâ produced by his audience uncovers and enumerates the different types of âmisreadingâ that occurred amongst his group of respondents, classifying these into such categories as âstock responsesâ, âtechnical presuppositionsâ, sentimentality and inhibition.74 Yet while Richards was concerned with the number of misreadings that his respondents produced, he also believed that âthe deficiencies so noticeable in the protocol writers […] are not native inalterable defects in the average human mind. They are due in a large degree to mistakes that can be avoided, and to bad training.â75 To address this lack of analytical training, Richards proposed a model of reading that turned the study of texts into a question of exegesis, involving âan intellectual analysis of the Total Meaningâ into its contributory components of sense, feeling, tone, intention and form.76 This method of reading diverged radically from the Cambridge model of âliterature, life and thoughtâ, as it isolated the text from its historical and biographical contexts and placed the emphasis firmly on the readerâs interpretative capacity. This anti-historicism was perhaps inevitable, given Richardsâs dislike of history as both an academic discipline and a way of understanding the world, and his mistrust of biographical approaches.77 Even so, it did not prevent his critical method from being adapted by the new Cambridge English Faculty when it was founded in 1926. The revised English Tripos of that year gave a central place to practical criticism, in the form of a compulsory paper entitled âPassages of English Prose and Verse for Critical Commentâ.78 This was to be the first stage in a process that would see practical criticism becoming a staple method in the teaching of English at both school and university level, offering self-contained exercises that emphasised rigour, difficulty and exactitude. Richards has subsequently come to be seen as a central figure in the development of English critical method- ology, offering âa precisely articulated theory of criticism, together with an analytical method for its classroom useâ.79 Indeed, in the words of Wallace Martin, Richardsâs conception of criticism is âalmost without precedent in the English-speaking worldâ: innovative, far-reaching, and a crucial contribution to the disciplinary development of English.80 Such claims on behalf of Richards are common, and it is sometimes difficult to see him in any other light than as the founder of modern English studies, contributing a precise, scientific method to a subject that had still not found a unified academic identity. Nevertheless, it is important to recall Richardsâs own intentions in formulating practical criticism. He did not want his techniques to be applied in a program- matic manner, and felt that criticism required a âsubtle senseâ of meaning and intention rather than the crude application of a fixed method.81 He also expressed a profound mistrust of approaches that offered âstatistical inquiries into the âefficiencyâ of different forms of composition, into types of imagery, into the relative frequency of verbs and adjectivesâ.82 His vision of interpretation was one that he wished to communicate to society at large, rather than restricting it to the narrow world of academia: it is important to note that it was a theory of interpretation per se, and not specifically one of literary interpretation. However radical it may have been, a critical method that had no influence outside the universities would have been a failure, judged by Richardsâs own criteria. As a result, Richardsâs contribution to the academic study of English must be assessed with caution. Practical criticism was an important innovation in critical method, especially in a faculty that was increasingly concerned with the need to bring rigour and objectivity to English studies.83 Yet Richards intended it to be a generalist technique rather than part of a specialist programme of study. The uncovering of meaning, through a meticulous process of interpretation, was essential to Richardsâs  conceptions of value, experience and the mind, and was therefore central to his hopes for the regeneration of humanity: it could not be seen as a mere scholarly pursuit.